alt Scientific Realism: A Brief Introduction

In the philosophy of science there is a debate on the side of scientific realism and those who are opposite to it, namely antirealism or instrumentalism.

 

There is a fairly classic debate in philosophy on two opposing camps. The next debate took place on the realism and idealism camps. Realism argues that there is a physical world that is independent of human assumptions and perceptions. Idealism rejects this view, and claims that the physical world depends on human assumptions and perceptions. To most people the possibility of realism sounds more plausible than idealism. Realism seems more compatible with common sense because the facts out there are actually waiting to be discovered.

 

The differences of opinion on realism and idealism are also included in the metaphysical discussion. The focus of this paper is more specifically on the debate in the context of the philosophy of science, which from certain factors has a wedge with the metaphysical debate. The debate in the philosophy of science takes place on the side of scientific realism and on the opposite side of it, namely antirealism or instrumentalism.

 

Then what is scientific realism (or scientific realism)? Realism has the idea that science aims to provide a correct description of the world. So, a good scientific theory is one that describes the world too much (Okasha 2016: p. 55). To clarify our understanding of scientific realism, we will see further understanding from three aspects, namely: ontological or metaphysical factors, semantic factors, and epistemological factors.

 

Ontologically, scientific realism relies on the inspiration that there is a world that does not depend on the mind, which science investigates. Semantically, scientific realism is based on the idea that all claims about scientific entities (including processes, characteristics or properties, relations) have a value that can be determined as true or false. Epistemologically, scientific realism holds on to the inspiration that scientific/theoretical claims are claims that contain knowledge about the world or knowledge that contains descriptions of the world (Chakravartty 2017).

 

In contrast to scientific realism, antirealists have the idea that the object of science is to arrive at a reasonably empirical theory, in the sense of being able to correctly predict the results of experiments and observations. In other words, for antirealists, the question of whether a theory is too descriptive of the world is unimportant.

 

This difference of opinion on realism and anti-realism is getting sharper when examining what are called unobservable entities. Take for example suppose that in physics, physics has reached the stage where it mentions entities like atoms, electrons, quarks. Such entities cannot be seen directly, in the sense that they are not supported by tools. The realist group argues that the physical theory that examines subsequent entities is a theory that is too descriptive of the world (Okasha 2016: p. 55).

 

For anti-realists, these entities are only understood as an entity that helps predict the observed phenomena. In an attempt to be more aware, we take for example the kinetic theory of gases. This theory essentially proves that each volume of gas has a number of moving entities.

 

This entity refers to a molecule which is also an unobservable entity. From this theory we can take some consequences, suppose that when a hot air balloon is placed in the sun it will explode. Why did that happen? because of the increase in temperature in the balloon.

 

Returning to anti-realism, according to him, whether the air in the balloon contains moving molecules or not is not an important case. The important thing about the theory is because it can predict observations or because it predicts that if a balloon is placed in the sun it will explode. Therefore, antirealism is often labeled as instrumentalism because for instrumentalism, scientific theory is only used as an instrument that helps identify and predict the observed phenomena.

 

One of the inspirations that helped antirealists was the inspiration that proved that we cannot gain knowledge of unobservable entities, because they are beyond human reach. The pessimistic idea, if we draw it out, originates from empiricism which proves that human knowledge is limited to what can be experienced (Okasha 2016: p. 56).

 

Another idea on the anti-realist side comes from the logical positivism group. The ontological beliefs and questions held by scientific realism about a world independent of human assumptions are nonsense and meaningless. The discussion about how the relationship between science and reality is a discussion that is considered a waste of time. For this group, scientific propositions are said to be meaningful insofar as they refer to and can be interpreted in terms of experienced sensations. Like empiricism, this group holds that unobservable entities are beyond our reach. Language and assumptions cannot go that far (Godfrey-Smith 2003: pp. 180-181).

 

Having seen a little difference of opinion between the two groups, we now come to the section on what arguments support the position of scientific realism. The first argument is the'no miracle argument'or argument without magic. Theories that presuppose unobservable entities are empirically successful, in the sense that they can lead to good predictions of macroscopic phenomena. In addition, these theories are also successfully applied in technology.

 

From the explanation above, the argument without miracles proves that it would be an extraordinary coincidence if unobservable entities such as electrons and atoms were considered to not exist, while on the other hand the theory that presupposes these entities could predict macroscopic phenomena accurately and successfully was applied. in technology. In other words, these unobservable entities must be considered too present if they are not to witness the successful prediction and application of science in technology as a miracle (Okasha 2016: p. 59).

 

An argument without magic can be expressed more in the following form:

 

P

The best explanation for the fact P is that Q is true

Therefore, Q is true

P refers to the fact that science can predict phenomena accurately and is successfully applied to technology. Whereas"Qrefers to unobservable entities as being too existent, not merely useful entities insofar as it can predict the common phenomenon with accuracy. Put another way, the best explanation for successful prediction and application is due to the subsequent existence of unobserved entities (Rosenberg and McIntyre 2020: pp. 141-142).

 

The second argument is about the difference between observable and unobservable entities. As far as we take it for granted that chairs, desks, and laptops are observable entities, electrons, atoms, and quarks are unobservable entities. However, in reality the next difference is quite problematic philosophically. Further debates are also in principle unlikely to be made together firmly.

 

Why is this argument said to help the position of scientific realism? Because anti-realists argue that science cannot give us knowledge of unobservable entities, which implicitly assumes there is a clear distinction between what is observed and what is not. If this distinction cannot be expressed consciously and satisfactorily, then antirealism is in a rather problematic position (Okasha 2016: pp. 62-63).

 

In response to this second argument, anti-realists can evade by arguing that this argument merely shows the ambiguity of the meaning of observable and unobservable entities. The ambiguity of meaning for the antirealist does not imply that the distinction between observable and unobservable entities does not exist. However, anti-realists still need to provide additional explanations as to why knowledge of unobservable entities is impossible.

 

Thus a brief explanation of scientific realism and the response to it. Of course, the two arguments that are referred to as supporting the position of scientific realism have various responses and challenges.

 

Bibliography


  • Chakravartty, Anjan. 2017. “Scientific Realism.” Plato Stanford. Retrieved (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scientific-realism/).
  • Godfrey Smith, Peter. 2003. An Introduction to The Philosophy of Science: Theory and Reality. London: The University of Chicago Press.
  • Okasha, Samir. 2016. Philosophy Of Science: A Very Short Introduction. United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
  • Rosenberg, Alex, and Lee McIntyre. 2020. Philosophy of Science: A Contemporary Introduction. New York: Routledge.

Post a Comment